Resurrecting Candrakīrti - Selections

Disputes in the Tibetan Creation of Prāsaṅgika

CHAPTER 1: Indian Discovery of Candrakīrti

Prominent Tibetan scholars of the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries uniformly speak of a Prāsaṅgika school of Madhyamaka (“Middle Way”), founded by the Indians Buddhapālita (c. 500) and Candrakīrti (c. 570–640), developed in India—in some accounts by a lineage of mostly unlettered disciples but always including such luminaries as Śāntideva (early eighth century) and Atiśa (c. 982–1054)—and later propagated in Tibet. The Tibetan systematizers likewise speak of clear differences between the Prāsaṅgika and Svātantrika interpretations of Madhyamaka and of the superiority of Prāsaṅgika in elucidating the “true thought” of Nāgārjuna (c. 200), the founder of Madhyamaka. In this vein, Candrakīrti is said to have “refuted” Bhāvaviveka (c. 500–570), the “founder” of the Svātantrika interpretation, and established the preeminence of Prāsaṅgika through writing his commentary on Nāgārjuna’s Fundamental Treatise on the Middle. While the precise nature of the Prāsaṅgika-Svātantrika division was debated in the Kagyu, Sakya, and Geluk schools throughout the fourteenth to eighteenth centuries and in the nyingma school in the nineteenth century, there was no disagreement that just such a division accurately reflected Indian Buddhist developments of the sixth and seventh centuries. Tibetan scholarship on this distinction, from the fourteenth century into the present, has influenced a great deal of contemporary scholarship that continues to speak of two schools of Indian, and then Tibetan, Madhyamaka.

However, the Indian textual record presents a remarkably different view than fifteenth-century Tibetan scholars’ accounts. When we consider this record, we must conclude that Candrakīrti, rather than forming a school of Madhyamaka and triumphing over or refuting Bhāvaviveka, was in fact largely ignored in his day and for some three hundred years in both India and Tibet. Jayānanda (twelfth century) is the only known Indian commentator on the works of Candrakīrti, whereas there were eight Indian commentaries on Nāgārjuna’s Fundamental Treatise on the Middle and twenty-one Indian commentaries on Maitreya’s Ornament for Realization. The lineage of Indian Prāsaṅgika disciples stretching from Candrakīrti through Śāntideva and extending to Atiśa, the supposed progenitor of Prāsaṅgika in Tibet, varies widely in the Tibetan accounts and rarely includes figures known elsewhere. Furthermore, the argument from silence against Candrakīrti’s importance in India is bolstered by the fact that none of these shadowy figures is known by Tibetan scholars to have written on Madhyamaka (or anything else). This absence of any reported texts strongly suggests that, unlike the many volumes known to Tibetan scholars to have existed in India or Tibet in the past but no longer accessible to them or to us, no such texts by these figures ever existed. Rather, these figures would seem to represent Tibetan historians’ acknowledgment of great gaps in the Prāsaṅgika “lineage” and their attempts to fill in these holes with names, if not writings.

One can infer that the very survival of Candrakīrti’s writings down to the time of Jayānanda could only have been brought about by some kind of following, whether Candrakīrti’s writings were preserved in monastic libraries or transmitted in scribal families. Most strongly, we can imagine the existence of a marginal school of thought that did not champion Candrakīrti with new treatises (at least none that survived even until the time of Jayānanda) but studied and preserved his texts. It may have been this sense of a “lineage” that Tibetan authors imagined and attempted to enliven with names. A school, family, or library preserving Candrakīrti’s writings furthermore provides a more coherent picture of how his texts could later be popularized.

While the ongoing search for Sanskrit manuscripts could one day turn up a treatise from an early member of a putative Candrakīrti following, recent discoveries strengthen the case that Candrakīrti’s popularity arose long after his death. Studies of the recently recovered eighteen-folio Lakṣaṇaṭīkā show it to be a series of notes composed mostly in Sanskrit (with parts of four folios consisting of Tibetan notes) on three of Candrakīrti’s compositions. The colophons to the texts that the “Lakṣaṇaṭīkā” was bundled with lead Yonezawa tentatively to conclude that these comments stem from Abhayākaragupta (c. 1025–1125) through the pen of Nur Dharmadrak, who served as the scribe. While attributing these comments to Abhayākaragupta will require a great deal of further investigation into this manuscript and comparison with his known writings, the dating of the text seems secure, given Nur Dharmadrak’s role. A late eleventhto early twelfth-century frame for these important notes on several of Candrakīrti’s major writings aligns well with the surviving evidence for Indian interest in his work. Thus, at present we can deduce that Candrakīrti’s writings did not spawn a literary tradition for many hundreds of years, with Jayānanda’s commentary and the “Lakṣaṇaṭīkā” representing the earliest known works that take Candrakīrti as their subject matter.

The silence of Candrakīrti’s supposed Middle Way adversaries rings even more tellingly. While Avalokitavrata (c. 700) in his subcommentary on Bhāvaviveka’s Lamp for Wisdom mentions Candrakīrti in a list of Indian scholars who wrote commentaries on Nagārjuna’s Fundamental Treatise on the Middle, he says nothing about Candrakīrti’s lengthy criticisms of Bhāvaviveka. One can well assume that, in the Indian commentarial tradition, if Avalokitavrata deemed Candrakīrti’s attacks damaging, it would have been incumbent upon him to respond. His silence, in an otherwise extensive treatise (spanning three volumes in Tibetan translation), suggests that he viewed Candrakīrti’s criticisms as insignificant, not worthy of response, perhaps not even as serious philosophy.

Likewise, the important Mādhyamikas Śāntarakṣita (eighth century) and Kamalaśīla (c. 740–95) remained silent on Candrakīrti. Their extensive use of the Buddhist epistemological tradition, to an even greater degree than Bhāvaviveka, would require their responses to Candrakīrti’s attacks on that tradition, had they viewed his attacks to be damaging. Both authors, instead, were more concerned with Dharmapāla’s critique—from a Yogācāra viewpoint—of the feasibility of joining epistemology with Madhyamaka ontology. Furthermore, in Ichigō’s analysis, Kamalaśīla worked to refine Bhāvaviveka’s and Śāntarakṣita’s views, arguing against subtleties in their writings rather than concern himself with the widely divergent views of Candrakīrti. The wide success of Śāntarakṣita’s and Kamalaśīla’s Yogācāra-Madhyamaka interpretation, an interpretation well at odds with Candrakīrti’s own, suggests Candrakīrti’s insignificance during this time. In contradistinction to what fifteenth-century Tibetan authors state, the textual evidence leads one to conclude that Candrakīrti was a marginal figure in his day and uninfluential in India until the close of the first millennium.

Tibetan evidence—translations of Sanskrit Madhyamaka texts and native Tibetan commentaries and doxographies—from the establishment of Buddhism in Tibet until 1000 show a similar disinterest in Candrakīrti. Whereas a wealth of important Madhyamaka texts by Nāgārjuna, Āryadeva, Buddhapālita, Bhāvaviveka, and Śāntideva were translated during the “early diffusion” (snga dar) of Buddhism into Tibet, Candrakīrti’s major writings were not translated into Tibetan until the eleventh century. Only two of his commentaries, both on two of Nāgārjuna’s texts, Sixty Stanzas of Reasoning and Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness, were translated in the “early diffusion.” These commentaries would be likely candidates for translation as they represent the only Indian commentaries on these important Nāgārjuna texts. In cases where Tibetans had a choice of commentarial tradition, for instance with Nāgārjuna’s Fundamental Treatise on the Middle, Candrakīrti was left out.

As is well known, Śāntarakṣita and Kamalaśīla, both later categorized as Svātantrika-Mādhyamikas, were instrumental in the early diffusion of Buddhism in Tibet, the former credited with creating the first monastery in Tibet at Samyé and ordaining the first Tibetan monks and the latter, his student, credited with establishing the orthodox “gradual path” at the purported Great Debate at Samyé. Their most important Madhyamaka texts were translated during the early diffusion, along with those by another key Indian author, Jñānagarbha, who blended components of Dharmakīrti’s epistemology with Madhyamaka thought. Not surprisingly then, the first Tibetan doxographies by Yeshé Dé (Ye shes sde) and Kawa Peltsek (Ka ba dpal brtsegs) in the eighth century esteem the Yogācāra-Madhyamaka synthesis created by Śāntarakṣita and Kamalaśīla as the highest Buddhist school of thought. Bhāvaviveka’s Sautrāntika-Madhyamaka is ranked second. Candrakīrti is not mentioned. No Prāsaṅgika school is identified nor do we see the appellation, “Svātantrika,” which—as discussed in chapter 2—is first employed only in the twelfth century, in contradistinction to Candrakīrti’s views. This earlier bifurcation of Madhyamaka into Yogācāra and Sautrāntika sub-streams, to the apparent exclusion of Candrakīrti’s views, appears also in Rongzom Chokyi Zangpo’s (Rong zom Chos kyi bzang po, eleventh century) three doxographical works, perhaps our earliest sources for the Madhyamaka of the “later diffusion” (phyi dar) of Buddhism in Tibet.

The Indian and Tibetan evidence point to an eleventh-century resurrection of Candrakīrti’s writings in India and a twelfth-century birth of the Prāsaṅgika movement in Tibet. In addition to detailing Candrakīrti’s Indian rise, this chapter discusses the fragmented evidence that illuminates the philosophical and doctrinal issues (treated more fully in chapters 3 through 5) engendered by his writings that polarized Indian and Tibetan Buddhists in this period. The central issue around which Candrakīrti’s fame grew was his perceived denial of “valid cognition” —the epistemological enterprise foundational to Indian thought from at least the sixth century. As will be seen, both Candrakīrti’s supporters and detractors saw his philosophy as denying the validity of ordinary human cognition in the project of reaching enlightening knowledge. This denial held far-reaching ramifications, extending from a low appraisal of the value of human intellect to the very nature of buddhahood.

Reviving Candrakīrti’s Critique of Ultimate Valid Cognition
As mentioned above, fifteenth century and later Tibetan authors frequently group Śāntideva’s writings with Candrakīrti’s as “Prāsaṅgika” and place him in a lineage stretching from Candrakīrti down to these authors themselves. Śāntideva is the one figure in these lineage lists prior to Atiśa about whom we have literary information. However, Śāntideva’s own writings make no reference to Candrakīrti nor to any other of the figures that Tibetan historians would place in a lineage between Candrakīrti and Śāntideva. Śāntideva’s surviving writings, consisting of poetry and comments interspersing his collection of sūtra fragments, allow a great deal of interpretive room. Several verses from the ninth chapter of Engaging in the Bodhisattva’s Practice echo sentiments found in Candrakīrti’s writings, especially the denial that ultimate truth is a referent of human intellect, the explanation of ultimate truth as “non-seeing,” and the refutation of self-cognizing consciousness.

Despite this seeming harmony between Candrakīrti and Śāntideva, it is important to note that this text was commented upon from a decidedly non-Prāsaṅgika standpoint both in the early diffusion of Buddhism in Tibet and during the later spread. Saito points to two Indian commentaries, likely the earliest, that treat Śāntideva’s text from a Yogācāra-Madhyamaka perspective. From the later diffusion, we see commentaries to the text by Ngok the Translator and Chapa, both of whom opposed Candrakīrti’s views. Furthermore, Śāntideva’s text grew over hundreds of years: the version cataloged in the Den karma collection (c. 800) is 600 stanzas in length, while that preserved in the Dunhuang caves (dated to before 950) contains 701.5 stanzas. Both are far shorter than the present canonical version in 913 stanzas. The fact that Śāntideva’s stanzas were important to Yogācāra-Mādhyamikas and the growth of the text heightens our uncertainty as to which views we may ascribe to the eighth-century Śāntideva.

While we thus cannot with any certainty show a historical link between Śāntideva and Candrakīrti, over two hundred years after Śāntideva wrote, his commentator, Prajñākaramati (950–1030), ties Śāntideva’s views to Candrakīrti. Prajñākaramati cites Candrakīrti’s Entrance to the Middle repeatedly in his commentary to Śāntideva’s Engaging in the Bodhisattva’s Practice. Prajñākaramati relies particularly heavily on Candrakīrti in his comments on Śāntideva’s proclamation of the two truths (satyadvaya, stanza IX.2), citing Entrance to the Middle four times (stanzas VI.23, 25, 28, and 29), a lengthy sūtra passage found in Entrance to the Middle, and three sūtra passages found in Candrakīrti’s Clear Words. The strongest link we may establish is not between Candrakīrti and Śāntideva but between Candrakīrti and Prajñākaramati. The latter is the earliest Indian author that we know of to express overt enthusiasm for Candrakīrti’s writings.

Vibhūticandra (c. 1200) likewise employs stanzas from Entrance to the Middle in his comments on Śāntideva’s stanza IX.2. Vibhūticandra was part of the last entourage of Indian paṇḍitas to travel to Central Tibet in 1204; he traveled with Śākya Śrībhadra (1127/1145–1225/1243), with whom the extremely influential Tibetan scholar Sakya Paṇḍita (1182–1251) worked. As will be discussed in more detail in chapter 2, Sakya Paṇḍita was the first to adopt the Prāsaṅgika position in the Sakya school. Vibhūticandra, then, may have been partly responsible for this development within Sakya.

Śāntideva’s brief stanza, in which ultimate truth is declared outside the realm of human intellect, reads:

It is asserted that there are two truths—obscurational and ultimate. The ultimate is not a referent of awareness; awareness is said to be obscurational.

Classical Indian aesthetics valued poetic brevity; elaborating on meaning was left to a commentator. So while Śāntideva may have meant his stanza to echo an important theme in Candrakīrti’s writings that the ultimate “is just not an object of consciousness,” Prajñākaramati makes the first certain connection between the two and is the earliest commentator to explicate this theme in either Candrakīrti’s or Śāntideva’s works. Prajñākaramati elaborates at some length, writing that Śāntideva’s “awareness” means “all consciousness,” that the ultimate “surpasses the sphere of all consciousness,” and that it is “impossible to bring [the ultimate] within the sphere of awareness in any way.” He later notes, “All awareness, whether having an object or not having an object, has a nature of conceptuality and all conceptuality has a nature of ignorance.” Prajñākaramati also utilizes Candrakīrti’s comparison of objects of consciousness to the flickering hairs seen by those suffering from eye diseases, suggesting that just as all awareness is flawed with ignorance, so all objects of awareness are unreal.

In linking Candrakīrti’s and Śāntideva’s texts on the radical separation of human consciousness and the ultimate, Prajñākaramati establishes an important tenet of his interpretation of Madhyamaka and shows a lengthy pedigree of the tenet, drawing upon a sūtra in which the Buddha himself makes such a proclamation; he establishes a tradition of exegesis, the beginnings of what would become a Prāsaṅgika interpretation of Buddhist philosophy. Furthermore, he posits a radical separation of ultimate truth and those things known by ordinary consciousness: what we call knowledge he calls ignorance. Such a vast divide between ordinary consciousness and knowledge of the ultimate runs directly counter to the epistemological project of establishing the valid foundations of all knowledge, conventional and ultimate, engaged in by Mādhyamikas since the sixth century. Indeed, Prajñākaramati concludes his discussion of ultimate truth by stating that only āryas—advanced bodhisattvas who realize emptiness directly—have valid cognition concerning the ultimate. This conclusion, too, is lifted directly from Candrakīrti’s Entrance to the Middle. However, unlike in Candrakīrti’s India, Prajñākaramati’s great divide separating conventional knowledge from knowledge of the ultimate sparked debate among Mādhyamikas on both sides of the Himalayas. Candrakīrti’s rejection of valid cognition in ultimate pursuits ran directly counter to the tenor of Indian philosophy that in his day was dominated by epistemological concerns across religious traditions. In such a religious climate, his separation could not be taken seriously. By Prajñākaramati’s time, Candrakīrti’s conservative bent could be recast as a unique and viable Madhyamaka interpretation.

As noted above, Atiśa (Dīpaṅkaraśrījñāna), a junior contemporary of Prajñākaramati, is commonly credited with establishing Prāsaṅgika in Tibet. His Introduction to the Two Truths twice praises Candrakīrti, once for Candrakīrti’s presentation of the two truths and once for Candrakīrti’s understanding of ultimate truth. The latter passage reads:

Candrakīrti is the disciple of Nāgārjuna
Who saw the truth of the final nature.
The truth of the final nature is to be realized
According to the instructions of his lineage.

Leading up to this stanza, Atiśa denied the validity of both forms of valid cognition accepted by Buddhists—direct perception and inference—to realize the ultimate and further rejected the ability of conceptual and non-conceptual consciousness to realize it. Clearly, his praise of Candrakīrti’s understanding of ultimate truth references Candrakīrti’s denial that the ultimate can be known by human intellect.

In this same text, Atiśa refers favorably to Bhāvaviveka, the supposed founder of the Svātantrika interpretation of Madhyamaka, over whom Candrakīrti’s Prāsaṅgika supposedly triumphed. Atiśa also translated into Tibetan two of Bhāvaviveka’s most important texts, Heart of the Middle and its autocommentary, Blaze of Reasoning. These two texts were translated at the request of Ngok Lekpay Sherab, whose monastic institute staunchly opposed Candrakīrti’s views. Elsewhere, Atiśa lists Bhāvaviveka and Candrakīrti as authoritative interpreters of Madhyamaka, along with Nāgārjuna, Āryadeva, Śāntideva, and Atiśa’s own teacher, Bodhibhadra. We might conclude that Atiśa saw Candrakīrti and Bhāvaviveka as upholding equally valid positions. Ruegg notes that, “In Dīpaṅkaraśrījñāna’s time and circle, Bhavya’s and Candrakīrti’s schools of the Madhyamaka were apparently not clearly differentiated by distinct designations and they were evidently being studied side by side.” Extending Ruegg’s point, the very issues that would polarize Bhāvaviveka’s and Candrakīrti’s writings into separate schools of thought were only in Atiśa’s day coming to be elucidated.

However, Atiśa’s endorsement of Candrakīrti may be the earliest instance of an Indian author favoring Candrakīrti over Bhāvaviveka. When we look more closely at Atiśa’s Introduction to the Two Truths, we see that his praise of Bhāvaviveka was misplaced. He wrote “The Master scholar Bhavya stated that [the ultimate] is not realized by either conceptual nor nonconceptual consciousness.” Lindtner adeptly identifies a very similar statement, to which Atiśa likely referred, in the Jewel Lamp of the Middle, a text attributed to Bhāvaviveka. The Bhāvaviveka who wrote the Jewel Lamp of the Middle, and who claims to be the author of Heart of the Middle and Blaze of Reasoning as well, refers favorably to Candrakīrti’s Entrance to the Middle, and so must post-date him. The Bhāvaviveka who wrote Heart of the Middle and Lamp for Wisdom—a section of which Candrakīrti critiqued in detail—preceded Candrakīrti, making a common attribution impossible. The statement that Atiśa endorses from the Jewel Lamp of the Middle shows much more affinity for Candrakīrti’s views—at least as presented by Atiśa—than those expressed in Heart of the Middle.

More tellingly, Atiśa criticizes another of Bhāvaviveka’s views (without mentioning Bhāvaviveka by name). He writes, “ultimate truth is only one; others assert that it is two.” As we have seen, Candrakīrti and Prajñākaramati rejected the applicability of valid cognition to ultimate truth. Anticipating such criticism, Bhāvaviveka wrote of two kinds of ultimate consciousnesses, which realize two kinds of objects:

The ultimate is of two types: one engages thoroughly effortlessly, passes beyond the world, is undefiled, and lacks proliferation; the second engages with thorough effort, accords with the collection of merit and wisdom, is called “pure worldly wisdom,” and possesses proliferations.

Bhāvaviveka explains that the second kind of ultimate consciousness realizes ultimate truth inferentially; he explains how inference is utilized in knowing ultimate truth. In rejecting that ultimate truth is two, Atiśa rejects Bhāvaviveka’s solution to inference’s utility. Atiśa further states that, “The deluded whose vision is narrow say that the two [kinds of valid cognition, direct perception and inference] realize emptiness.” Atiśa’s critique of Bhāvaviveka’s use of valid cognition in general and inference in particular, seemingly inspired by Candrakīrti’s views, is perhaps the first implicit hierarchical ranking of Candrakīrti over Bhāvaviveka. The validity of human cognition in knowing emptiness is the litmus test in Atiśa’s ranking.

Apart from Atiśa’s attributions, the later Bhāvaviveka’s work itself reveals the impact of Candrakīrti’s views and represents a further mark of his growing influence. It may well be that the passage from Blaze of Reasoning (Tarkajvāla) cited just above does not anticipate Candrakīrti’s criticism but, in fact, responds to it. Ruegg utilizes the work of Ejima, who distinguishes an “ur-Tarkajvāla” from a revised version, to suggest that many parts of Blaze of Reasoning were not written by the Bhāvaviveka who wrote Heart of the Middle (the stanzas upon which Blaze of Reasoning comments) but by the later Bhāvaviveka who wrote the Jewel Lamp of the Middle. Furthermore, the commonalities between the Jewel Lamp of the Middle, the Compendium of Meanings of the Middle (Madhyamakārthasaṃgraha), and certain parts of Blaze of Reasoning suggest that the same hand (Bhāvaviveka II) composed them. The passage I have cited from Blaze of Reasoning can likely be considered a later accretion as the Compendium of Meanings of the Middle likewise posits a two-fold ultimate truth, a figurative ultimate (paryāyaparamārtha) that can be expressed in language and grasped by conceptual thought and a non-figurative ultimate that is beyond expression and thought. This closely mirrors the two-fold ultimate explained in the Blaze of Reasoning passage. Bhāvaviveka II in these two texts may have been the earliest Middle Way author to respond to Candrakīrti’s critique of utilizing valid cognition in the pursuit of emptiness, showing how a certain kind of ultimate truth can fall within the range of formal reasoning.

Bhāvaviveka II clearly identifies with his namesake’s epistemological convictions, as is evident in both the Jewel Lamp of the Middle and the Compendium of Meanings of the Middle. In these two texts, he evinces views similar to Jñānagarbha’s Madhyamaka adoption of Dharmakīrti’s “causal efficacy”— which Dharmakīrti took as the mark of ultimate existence—as the mark of conventional existence. Both texts further adopt Jñānagarbha’s characterization of conventional existence as “existing as it appears,” with the Jewel Lamp repeating Jñānagarbha’s corollary that the conventional world “exists when not analyzed.” Bhāvaviveka II’s commitment to the Madhyamaka epistemological project of his namesake extends the earlier figure’s ideas with those of the eighth-century confluence of Madhyamaka and Dharmakīrti’s philosophy.

However, the Jewel Lamp of the Middle evinces several points conceded to Candrakīrti’s critique of valid cognition. The Jewel Lamp denies that those who use inference can know reality through their analyses, states that ordinary sense perception does not constitute valid cognition, and opines that valid cognition of obscurational truth only functions within worldly conventions, for those whose vision is narrow. This combination of delimiting the scope of valid cognition while yet advancing criteria for the validity of certain kinds of conventional objects and conventional consciousnesses may represent the earliest attempt to reconcile Candrakīrti’s critique of the Buddhist epistemological tradition with the philosophy he opposed. This reconciliation would come to characterize Tibetan exegesis of Candrakīrti’s works by the late twelfth century.

The themes that we see Prajñākaramati and Atiśa drawing from Candrakīrti’s texts are amplified further in Jayānanda’s extensive commentary to Candrakīrti’s Entrance to the Middle, written in the mid-twelfth century (far from India, in the Tangut kingdom) and the only full-fledged commentary on Candrakīrti’s writings written by an Indic author. This text offers a fully developed presentation of the conflict Candrakīrti’s views engendered on the issue of the ultimate and the value of human intellect. In chapter 3, I examine Jayānanda’s understanding of pervasive ignorance that, as it does in Prajñākaramati’s presentation, characterizes all human consciousness. Jayānanda directly addresses the characteristic that Buddhist epistemologists employed to define valid cognition, “non-deceptive” (avisaṃvadin) or “unmistaken” (abhrānta), and declares that no human cognition meets this criterion. In chapters 4 and 5, I show that Jayānanda’s views on human ignorance led him to deny human consciousness any direct access to the ultimate. “Knowing” the ultimate becomes metaphorical; in reality, in the ultimate state consciousness ceases—“knowledge” of the ultimate cannot be understood as a cognitive event. These views become Jayānanda’s basis for denying the Mādhyamika’s use of formal inferences and the broad Epistemological project.

Another clear reference to Candrakīrti’s views on the inapplicability of valid cognition to ultimate truth was voiced by an eleventh-century figure also named Candrakīrti. He wrote Entrance to Middle Way Wisdom and translated it into Tibetan with Gö Kugpa Lhetse, a student of Atiśa. While brief— only eighteen stanzas in length—this text expresses several of the themes that we have seen Candrakīrti’s revivers singling out. He writes that, in the context of ultimate truth, “there is no thesis or reason,” thereby denying that inference has utility in knowing the ultimate. Having argued for the non-existence of mind and mental factors, thereby supporting one of the primary features of Candrakīrti’s views that generated controversy in the eleventh and twelfth centuries, Candrakīrti III considers the objection that such a denial contradicts perception; he responds that he does not refute the non-analytical view. Candrakīrti III’s “non-analytical” mirrored the first Candrakīrti’s injunction that “worldly, conventional truths are not to be analyzed.” Despite the brevity of Candrakīrti III’s only known text, his framing of the non-analytical view was important to Chapa who adopted this terminology in his portrayal of Candrakīrti’s system, which he argued against at length. Rather than preserved in an unbroken lineage established by Candrakīrti himself, we see Candrakīrti’s main texts—however they may have survived up to this point—receiving broader attention beginning around the year 1000. Śāntideva may have been aware of Candrakīrti’s ideas but did not develop them. Instead, important eleventhand twelfth-century Indian scholars suddenly took interest in these forgotten texts and saw in them a basis from which to criticize the widespread importance of valid cognition scholarship among Buddhist philosophers. The consistency with which Candrakīrti’s revivalists cited his critiques of valid cognition and his understanding of ultimate truth make clear the philosophical reasons for championing his interpretation of Madhyamaka. The following section explores some possible explanations for the sudden interest in Candrakīrti’s critique in the eleventh century, following hundreds of years of Mādhyamikas wrestling with the epistemological foundations and implications of Nāgārjuna’s views.

Candrakīrti and Tantra
Atiśa’s literary output testifies to his interest in tantric Buddhist theory and practice. We might assume, given the widespread enthusiasm for tantra among Buddhists of this period, that Prajñākaramati and Jayānanda also maintained interest in tantra. However, neither of these three scholars’ writings make any indication that their interest in Candrakīrti’s texts was at all tied to late Indian tantric Buddhism. This section explores the ideas of several authors who make just such an explicit connection and who suggest to us that Candrakīrti’s views enjoyed their first broad popularity due to the consonances between his ideas on ultimate truth, as well as the inapplicability of valid cognition to its pursuit, and tantric concerns.

Juxtaposing Candrakīrti and Tantras
An important reference to Candrakīrti from a tantric text of this time period is found in Sahajavajra’s commentary to Maitrīpāda’s Ten Stanzas on Reality. Here, what is said may not be as illuminating as the context in which Candrakīrti’s views are brought to bear. In discussing the second stanza, Sahajavajra endorses Nāgārjuna’s, Āryadeva’s, and Candrakīrti’s explanation of dependent arising (pratītyasamutpada). He further notes that Candrakīrti’s Entrance to the Middle presents the Indian Buddhist “Mind Only” teaching as requiring interpretation. While these two references do not allow a clear sense of why Sahajavajra singled out Candrakīrti’s interpretations, the fact that a late Indian tantric author cites him as an authority is illuminating. Maitrīpāda is often linked to Atiśa, either as Atiśa’s teacher or as a student whom Atiśa, in his role as abbot, had to expel from Vikramaśīla Monastery for Maitrīpāda’s illicit tantric practices. He is also an important source of writings on the tantric practice, Mahāmudrā; in fact, all of his writings, including Ten Stanzas on Reality, are included in the “Tantra Commentaries” (rgyud ’grel) section of the Tibetan canon. Tibetan Kagyu sources claim Maitrīpāda, along with Patsab nyimadrak, as the two sources of their Prāsaṅgika lineage.

Kagyu tradition and Sahajavajra’s citation suggest that Maitrīpāda held Candrakīrti’s interpretation of Madhyamaka. While Sahajavajra’s comment does not allow insight into just what about Candrakīrti’s views he found favorable, it establishes a link between Candrakīrti’s interpretation and the kinds of antinomian tantras that were created and disseminated across the Himalayas in the tenth and eleventh centuries. One can well imagine that Candrakīrti’s rejection of the established practices of valid cognition that so dominated scholastic Buddhism throughout the second part of the first millennium would appeal to the creators and practitioners of these tantras. Furthermore, Candrakīrti’s understanding of an ultimate beyond the scope of human cognition fits well with tantric portrayals of a pure, pristine ultimate state in which human consciousness—invariably intertwined with subjectobject duality—can play no role.

Another connection between Candrakīrti’s idea of the ultimate and late Indian Buddhist tantric concerns appears in the Compendium of Good Sayings, an anthology of citations from Buddhist texts that is dominated by extracts from “Highest Yoga Tantras” (anuttarayogatantra) but also contains nearly thirty stanzas from Candrakīrti’s Entrance to the Middle. The Compendium cites Candrakīrti’s statement on the relationship between obscurational truth and ultimate truth, linking it—as did Prajñākaramati and Jayānanda—with Śāntideva’s presentation of obscurational and ultimate truths. The Compendium also cites several of Candrakīrti’s stanzas that address the disparity between various conceptions of causality and the ultimate perspective, from which there is no causality at all. These stanzas are cited following Nāgārjuna’s famous denial of production from “four alternatives,” which, in Candrakīrti’s Clear Words, provided the occasion for Candrakīrti’s lengthy criticisms of formal inference’s usefulness in inducing knowledge of the ultimate. While the Compendium of Good Sayings cites only Candrakīrti’s verses from Entrance to the Middle, the import of his Clear Words is entailed: the Compendium endorses Candrakīrti’s interpretation of the ultimate, for which formal inference is useless but with which tantra is well in consonance.

Candrakīrti’s stanzas denying production from the “four alternatives” are preceded in the Compendium of Good Sayings by a similar statement there attributed to the noted tantric author, Saraha (but likely authored by the tantric Āryadeva), stating that reality is devoid of existence, nonexistence, both existence and non-existence, and neither. These stanzas of the tantric Āryadeva were adopted into at least four other texts composed by tantric authors in the early part of the eleventh century, including the Stainless Light commentary to the Kālacakra Tantra. The Compendium of Good Sayings’s juxtaposition of these stanzas with Candrakīrti’s refutation of production links Candrakīrti’s and tantric understandings of the ultimate, suggesting that Candrakīrti’s views were valued by proponents of late Indian Buddhist tantra for their utter rejection of the dualities of cause and effect (producer and produced), existence and non-existence. The consonances between Candrakīrti’s and late tantric views suggest that Candrakīrti’s rise in popularity was due, at least in part, to the rise of “Highest Yoga Tantras” in turn-of-the-millennium India.

Candrakīrti and the “Noble” Lineage
The Compendium of Good Sayings links Saraha, Nāgārjuna, and Candrakīrti, a connection well-attested in the “noble” (Ārya) lineage of the Guhyasamāja Tantra transmission. This lineage places three Middle Way luminaries— Nāgārjuna, Āryadeva, and Candrakīrti—as among the earliest to transmit the Guhyasamāja in India. The identity of these three tantric authors, all of whom wrote commentarial materials on the Guhyasamāja, with the Middle Way authors, all of whom flourished hundreds of years prior to the composition of the Guhyasamāja materials, seems to have been widely accepted among Indian and Tibetan Buddhists in the early years of the second millennium. As Wedemeyer points out, the assumed identity—likely on the part of the tantric authors themselves—was no coincidence: the tantric authors appropriated the names of Middle Way authors due to a sense of shared philosophy and as a means of utilizing the earlier authors’ authority. While a precise mapping of the philosophical consonances between the tantric authors and their Middle Way namesakes remains a desideratum, Isaacson has identified an excellent starting point, noting the strong correlation and textual parallelism between a statement of the “two stages” of Guhyasamāja yoga and Nāgārjuna’s classic pronouncement of the two truths.

Wedemeyer’s notion that tantric authors—or their students—sought to invoke the authority of earlier Middle Way personalities, a strongly credible thesis, only works if the Middle Way authors were in fact regarded as authorities. We have good reason to think that Nāgārjuna and Āryadeva had long been well respected as Mahāyāna luminaries. The “noble” lineage accords Candrakīrti status equal to Āryadeva, as a “son” of Nāgārjuna, perhaps our earliest indication of his new fame. Wedemeyer shows that Āryadeva’s major tantric work can be placed safely between 850 and 1000 of the common era and leans toward a more precise dating of the late ninth to early tenth centuries. We might place the tantric Candrakīrti in the same time frame, using the “brotherhood” model of the “noble” lineage. This would evince perhaps the earliest use of Candrakīrti’s authority, pre-dating Prajñākaramati and Atiśa by some decades. If the dating of the tantric Candrakīrti requires a shift forward roughly fifty years, his flourit would barely precede the time frame of Prajñākaramati’s and Atiśa’s citations of the Middle Way Candrakīrti. In any case, that the identity of the tantric and Middle Way Candrakīrtis was widely accepted in the eleventh century gives us good reason to connect the sudden interest in the Middle Way author with the rise of the “noble” lineage of the Guhyasamāja.

We have good evidence suggesting that nearly every champion of the Middle Way Candrakīrti identified him with the “noble” lineage author of the same name. As noted above, the Compendium of Good Sayings’s author seems to understand a strong connection between Saraha, Nāgārjuna, and the Middle Way Candrakīrti, making it likely that he saw the tantric and Middle Way Candrakīrtis as the same person. Atiśa, in the passage cited above in which he declares that “Candrakīrti is the disciple of Nāgārjuna” and proceeds to praise the non-tantric Candrakīrti’s view, seems to make just such an identification, as the author of Entrance to the Middle was not a disciple of any Nāgārjuna but the author of the Guhyasamāja commentary seems to have been. The principal Tibetan translator and exponent of the Middle Way Candrakīrti’s texts, Patsab Nyimadrak, also translated the tantric Candrakīrti’s Guhyasamāja commentary with his Indian teacher, Tilakakalaśa; both Patsab and Tilakakalaśa may thus have understood the authors of these texts to have been the same Candrakīrti. Certainly, later Tibetan authors viewed praise of the tantric Candrakīrti’s writings by the likes of naropāda to entail praise of the Middle Way Candrakīrti’s viewpoints (there being, in such a view, no difference between the tantric and Middle Way authors). We can say with some certainty that the success of the “noble” lineage lead to important changes in how late Indian Buddhists perceived the Middle Way Candrakīrti. The “noble” lineage makes Candrakīrti a direct disciple of Nāgārjuna, rather than a centuries-later commentator (as the Clear Words author would have been known), placing him on par with Āryadeva as “sons” of the venerable master. The “noble” lineage also places Candrakīrti just one step removed from the renowned tantric figure, Saraha, boosting his prestige further. The fame of the Guhyasamāja commentator may have been a primary factor in the belated success of Candrakīrti’s Entrance to the Middle and Clear Words. Indian Buddhists who esteemed the Guhyasamāja commentary felt compelled to take seriously Entrance to the Middle and Clear Words.

While serious consideration of the Middle Way Candrakīrti stemmed, at least in part, from the tantric Candrakīrti’s importance, the case of the tantric Bhāvaviveka requires further reflection on the Middle Way Candrakīrti’s impact. A Bhavyakīrti wrote sub-commentaries on both Nāgārjuna’s and Candrakīrti’s Guhyasamāja works. As discussed above, we see two Middle Way authors taking the name Bhāvaviveka, the first authoring Lamp for Wisdom and Heart of the Middle, the second authoring Jewel Lamp of the Middle, Compendium of Meanings of the Middle, and at least parts of Blaze of Reasoning as well. The latter Bhāvaviveka refers favorably to both Candrakīrti’s Entrance to the Middle and (a) Candrakīrti’s Seventy Stanzas on the Three Refuges apparently seeing no difference between those two authors. Ruegg suggests that this latter Bhāvaviveka, author of the Jewel Lamp of the Middle, may be the tantric Bhavyakīrti. If we accept this identity, we could date Bhāvaviveka II to the period immediately after the tantric Candrakīrti’s lifetime and immediately preceding Atiśa, who refers to Jewel Lamp of the Middle: right about the year 1000. This would place Bhāvaviveka II’s Middle Way views in a critical spot. As noted above, the Jewel Lamp, Compendium of Meanings, and parts of Blaze of Reasoning develop the Middle Way Epistemology blending of their namesake, suggest points of concession to the Middle Way Candrakīrti’s critique of that blend, and offer ways of responding to Candrakīrti’s critique. Set around the year 1000, these would be the earliest known attempts to incorporate and respond to Candrakīrti’s arguments.

Accepting the identity of Bhāvaviveka II and Bhavyakīrti could help answer a further problem with the late Bhāvaviveka. Why would Bhāvaviveka II, clearly indebted to the Middle Way Epistemology blend of his forbears, concede points to Candrakīrti’s critique of valid cognition? If he is the Bhavyakīrti sub-commentator on the Guhyasamāja, the explanation would be fairly straightforward: Bhāvaviveka II would be indebted to the tantric Candrakīrti’s opus and, like so many others in this period, would not distinguish that work from the Middle Way Candrakīrti’s corpus. The identity of the two Candrakīrtis forced him to consider the Middle Way Candrakīrti’s attacks on the applicability of valid cognition to knowledge of ultimate truth, to concede some points and offer answers to others. Bhāvaviveka II yet was so compelled by his namesake’s writings as to identify with that author, to add to at least one of the earlier figure’s texts (Blaze of Reasoning), and to compose still others in that author’s name. While some might think that this sketch would represent an extraordinarily conflicted individual, this cluster of views—tantra, Epistemology, and Candrakīrti’s Middle Way—would become increasingly common in the eleventh and twelfth centuries.

Assembling the Pieces: Tantra, Epistemology, and Candrakīrti
While Bhāvaviveka II’s writings may strengthen the notion that the Middle Way Candrakīrti’s rise was triggered by interest in the tantric Candrakīrti’s corpus, they also show that involvement with tantra need not occlude serious interest in the Buddhist Epistemological tradition. We certainly have ample evidence that tantra, Epistemology, and Middle Way philosophy lived together harmoniously. In eighth- and ninth-century India, when a major current of thought was Śāntarakṣita’s and Kamalaśīla’s synthesis of Middle Way and Epistemology, we see the tantric author of the Tattvasiddhi taking the name Śāntarakṣita. Like the Middle Way author, the Tattvasiddhi author relies heavily on the valid cognition tradition in order to prove (siddhi) his point, in this case that tantric practice leads one to realization of reality (tattva), expressed in tantric terminology as “great bliss.” The Tattvasiddhi (perhaps “Proof [that Tantric Practice Yields Knowledge of] Reality”) alerts us to how tantra was in some cases allied with the valid cognition tradition, particularly so prior to the rise of Candrakīrti’s fame. The Tattvasiddhi, and a good many other texts, suggest that Śāntarakṣita’s utilization of elements from the Epistemological tradition, as well as Yogācāra ontology, must have been seen by many to be consonant with mainstream Buddhist tantra.

The trends that we have seen in this chapter show the Middle Way Candrakīrti brought to life in opposition to the Epistemological tradition and in consonance with late Indian Buddhist tantra. Thus, certain strains of Buddhist tantric thought emerging in the late tenth century seem to have been less amenable to both the valid cognition project and, perhaps, Yogācāra. We have already seen some consonances between ideals of the tantric revivers of Candrakīrti’s writings and themes in those writings that critique the Epistemological tradition. The tantric Candrakīrti may well have been part of this opposition to the valid cognition tradition and to Yogācāra, which the Middle Way Candrakīrti critiqued at length in his Entrance to the Middle and Clear Words. Wayman suggests that the tantric Candrakīrti’s Guhyasamāja commentary evinces a move away from Yogācāra ontology, which was a much easier fit with tantra, toward a “pure” Madhyamaka interpretation of tantra. He notes the “Mādhyamika tone of commentary,” with its “avoidance of the typical Yogācāra vocabulary found in many other commentaries, especially in the Pañcakrama tradition.” Was Wayman simply projecting the Middle Way Candrakīrti’s anti-Yogācāra polemic onto the tantric Candrakīrti’s Guhyasamāja commentary, imagining something like a Yogācāra-Madhyamaka versus Prāsaṅgika-Madhyamaka divide within tantric exegesis?

While Wayman’s impressionistic characterization of the tantric Candrakīrti’s commentary does not provide textual support, we have softer evidence for a tantric move away from Yogācāra. Two of the tantric authors discussed above deploy the Middle Way Candrakīrti’s Yogācāra critique. We saw already that Sahajavajra’s commentary on Maitrīpāda’s Ten Stanzas on Reality praises Candrakīrti’s declaration in his Entrance to the Middle that Yogācāra is “interpretable.” Additionally, the Compendium of Good Sayings cites Candrakīrti’s refutation of Yogācāra in Entrance to the Middle, amid its collection of tantric extracts. These references alert us to the possibility that certain tantric exegetes attempted to move tantra away from its more comfortable home in Yogācāra ontology toward a “pure” Madhyamaka interpretation. In this attempt, the Middle Way Candrakīrti’s Yogācāra critique would prove useful. While Śāntarakṣita argued against Yogācāra as ultimately true, his adaptation of Yogācāra on the level of conventional truth and his widespread utilization of elements of Dharmakīrti’s valid cognition theory—which are often tied to Yogācāra—would have made his synthesis look less appealing to those wishing to distance tantra from Yogācāra.

While Candrakīrti’s rise coincided with strains of tantric thought that opposed the Buddhist Epistemological tradition, and perhaps Yogācāra as well, at least two Indian Buddhists found ways to harmonize the final developments of tantra and Epistemology, while either taking into account Candrakīrti’s views or adducing credible reasons to ignore them. Interestingly, these two scholars, Abhayākaragupta (c. 1025–1125) and Ratnākaraśānti (a contemporary of Prajñākaramati), both adopted a more critical approach to the identity of the Middle Way and tantric Candrakīrtis. Abhayākaragupta, an important scholar of both Nālandā and Vikramaśīla monasteries, wrote and translated numerous works on tantra and tantric practice and the Perfection of Wisdom literature in addition to translating Candrakīrti’s commentary on Nāgārjuna’s Seventy Stanzas on Emptiness with Nur Darmadrak. His Ornament for the Sage’s Thought refers to “the Master Candrakīrti” when citing Entrance to the Middle and to “Ārya Candra” when citing the tantric author. While Abhayākaragupta does not discuss the relationship between these two appellations, by distinguishing the two he seems to acknowledge some discrepancy between their views, if not their personages. Further, when he cites Candrakīrti’s Seventy Stanzas on the Three Refuges, he does not repeat Atiśa’s comment that Candrakīrti was the disciple of Nāgārjuna but instead notes that Candrakīrti “follows Nāgārjuna’s thought,” suggesting again that he distinguishes between the Middle Way Candrakīrti who was not Nāgārjuna’s disciple and the tantric Candrakīrti who was the tantric Nāgārjuna’s disciple.

Ratnākaraśānti explicitly distinguished between the views (but not the personages) of the Middle Way and tantric Candrakīrtis. While he believed that the same Candrakīrti wrote Entrance to the Middle and the Guhyasamāja commentary, he saw the former text espousing nihilism while only Candrakīrti’s tantric writings reflected true insight. Candrakīrti’s Middle Way corpus could be safely disregarded, representing merely his immature views.

The critical stances adopted by these two Indian polymaths, who both wrote extensively in the tantric and valid cognition traditions as well as on Madhyamaka, toward Candrakīrti’s corpus is matched by their either apologetical or critical approach to the Middle Way Candrakīrti’s views. Ratnākaraśānti was openly critical of what he portrayed as Candrakīrti’s “nihilism.” Abhayākaragupta’s citations of Candrakīrti’s Entrance to the Middle and its autocommentary are less openly critical, choosing to explain what Candrakīrti was “thinking” (saṃdhi, dgongs pa) when he made certain problematic declarations, including Candrakīrti’s proclamations that mind and mental factors cease upon buddhahood and that enlightenment consists in utter non-perception. Other citations are utilized as supports for a point Abhayākaragupta makes, with no further discussion of the passage; these points suggest his endorsement of certain of Candrakīrti’s views that proved useful in advancing his own.

Both authors take the tantric Candrakīrti as an authority but either openly or apologetically criticize the Middle Way Candrakīrti. While the rise of the tantric Candrakīrti contributed to reviving the Middle Way Candrakīrti, these two authors show that enthusiasm for one Candrakīrti need not entail support of the other. Ratnākaraśānti’s disavowal of the Middle Way Candrakīrti’s work and Abhayākaragupta’s apology show that not all tantric authors of this period found Candrakīrti’s ideas literally acceptable, particularly when those authors had strong ties to the valid cognition tradition. However, unlike in Śāntarakṣita’s day, neither author could simply ignore Entrance to the Middle. An eleventhor twelfth-century tantric author who wished to criticize Candrakīrti’s Middle Way views needed to suggest some method for differentiating those views from the position of the esteemed tantric Candrakīrti. We might even hypothesize that Ratnākaraśānti’s and Abhayākaragupta’s varying strategies suggest the growing authority of Candrakīrti’s Middle Way views in the perhaps century separating the two. In Ratnākaraśānti’s time (c. 1000), one could differentiate the Middle Way and tantric corpi and criticize the former. By the time Abhayākaragupta wrote Ornament for the Sage’s Thought in 1113, a distinction could still be drawn, but now problematic Middle Way assertions had to be explained away. Abhayākaragupta clearly disagreed with Candrakīrti’s views on buddhahood and ultimate truth but now felt compelled to explain Candrakīrti’s “thinking” on these issues.

Situating Candrakīrti’s rise within the broader currents of late Indian Buddhist thought allows us to appreciate both the complexity of the period that first gave his corpus serious consideration and the allegiances that his revivers made between his views and the tantric writing of the period. Whether or not Indian Buddhists uniformly confused the tantric Candrakīrti with his Middle Way namesake, eleventhand twelfth-century tantric authors consistently referred to Candrakīrti’s views on ultimate truth and the inapplicability of valid cognition to realizing ultimate truth as well as his arguments against Yogācāra. Candrakīrti’s position in late Indian Buddhists’ appraisal of why Madhyamaka was superior to Yogācāra, how tantra fit in with either system, and how or if valid cognition could be utilized within a Madhyamaka framework brought his texts their first widespread consideration. As we will see in the following chapter, this nexus of concerns fostered the development of a Prāsaṅgika school in twelfth-century Tibet, the success of which gave Candrakīrti’s texts the pre-eminent place in Tibetan Buddhist thought that they retain today.

Resurrecting Candrakīrti, Creating Prāsaṅgika
From the preceding, we can see that Candrakīrti’s views, while marginal in his own day, enjoyed a sudden popularity among important Indian Buddhists— but by no means among all Indian Buddhists nor to the exclusion of disparate interpretations of Madhyamaka—beginning in the early part of the eleventh century. We can also see that the central issue upon which Candrakīrti’s supporters elevated his once unpopular views revolved around the relationship between valid cognition and knowledge of the ultimate, which in turn led his supporters and detractors to portray the ultimate in disparate ways. To speak of a “Prāsaṅgika” movement—a championing of Candrakīrti’s texts—in the eleventh century, then, does not refer only to supporters of a mode of argumentation; it is not just a question of denying the validity of formal inference (or “inferences [accepted] in one’s own continuum,” svatantra-anumāna) in favor of apagogic (prasaṅga) reasoning. Crucial also to this movement were the ontological implications of reasoning. When Jayānanda, for the first time in the history of Indian Madhyamaka, writes of “Svātantrika,” he does not only refer (disparagingly) to Mādhyamikas who employ formal inferences but to an interpretation of the ultimate at odds with his own.

We see a great deal of debate among fourteenth-century and later Tibetan scholars, as well as among contemporary scholars, as to whether “Prāsaṅgika” and “Svātantrika” represent competing ontological visions or, instead, merely competing logical methods. Some recent scholarship focusing on “the Svātantrika-Prāsaṅgika distinction” has examined the early Indian evidence—the writings of Bhāvaviveka and Candrakīrti—to determine if ontological concerns entered into Bhāvaviveka’s procedural critique of Buddhapālita and Candrakīrti’s subsequent defense of Buddhapālita and counter-critique of Bhāvaviveka. Additionally, recent scholarship jumps forward some eight hundred years to examine the distinction that fourteenthand fifteenth-century Tibetan writers made between these two “schools” of Madhyamaka thought, particularly Tsongkhapa’s claim that the two schools hold divergent ontologies and several Sakya scholars’ claim, in rebuttal, that the distinction is purely procedural. This scholarship heightens our awareness that the Svātantrika-Prāsaṅgika distinction, as portrayed by Tibetan doxographies, is a distinction made by Tibetan scholars in order to categorize, harmonize, and explicate a wealth of Indian literature, the authors of which very likely never conceived of themselves as members of competing subschools of Madhyamaka. Scholarship has begun to highlight differences between Tibetan doxography and Indian historical reality.

However, scholarship has largely failed to examine the criteria that eleventhand twelfth-century scholars employed to elevate Candrakīrti’s Madhyamaka exegesis out of obscurity to a position where it came, at least in Tibet, to eclipse that of Śāntarakṣita (whose Madhyamaka had already eclipsed that of Bhāvaviveka three hundred years earlier). In sum, we have bypassed those who were the first to make a Prāsaṅgika-Svātantrika distinction. While the distinctions that these eleventhand twelfth-century scholars drew between Candrakīrti’s Madhyamaka—called “Prāsaṅgika” by twelfth-century Tibetans—and what Jayānanda and others called “Svātantrika” differ sharply from the distinction drawn by Tsongkhapa, clearly the issues in the eleventh and twelfth centuries are ontological and not only procedural. Our awareness of the important differences adduced by both Indian and Tibetan scholars in this period prevents us from downplaying the significance of this divide, which amounted to a lively debate over Candrakīrti’s importance, particularly concerning the status of ultimate truth.

This chapter has attempted to recover aspects of the historical rise of Candrakīrti, long after his death, and some of the philosophical and doctrinal trends that brought his rise to pass. In so doing, I have attempted to present a more historically plausible picture of Candrakīrti’s resurrection than the traditional view, which places his pre-eminence in his own lifetime. I have also tried to draw attention to those figures historically responsible for the rise of what came to be known as Prāsaṅgika. Candrakīrti surely saw himself as arguing against, even “refuting,” some of Bhāvaviveka’s views. However, the impact of his Bhāvaviveka critique upon the development of the Middle Way was not felt until centuries later. Jñānagarbha, Śāntarakṣita, and Kamalaśīla were far more concerned with arguing for Madhyamaka’s superiority over Yogācāra viewpoints than they were with establishing and defending Madhyamaka subschools. Any interest Śāntarakṣita had in defining a Madhyamaka subschool targeted Bhāvaviveka, not Candrakīrti. Candrakīrti was simply not an influential player in the Madhyamaka debates of the first millennium.

I have suggested that the appellation “Prāsaṅgika” can be applied to Candrakīrti’s revivalists, Prajñākaramati, Atiśa, and Jayānanda, particularly when we see that Jayānanda used its companion term, “Svātantrika,” to label his—and those whom he saw as Candrakīrti’s—opponents. However, regarding eleventhand twelfth-century Indian Madhyamaka, “Prāsaṅgika” does not refer to a distinct subschool but to an intellectual movement; we see important Middle Way figures supporting Candrakīrti’s long-silent philosophical positions. We do not see Indian authors conceiving of Candrakīrti’s views as excluding all else—of the authors investigated here, only Jayānanda may have eschewed all but Candrakīrti’s Madhyamaka. Nor do we see a polarization of Indian exegesis: Abhayākaragupta shows us how one may take Candrakīrti’s ideas seriously (how one may explain his thinking) while yet holding to something like “Svātantrika” viewpoints. While eleventh- and twelfth-century India saw a popularization of Candrakīrti’s views, the evidence supports the notion of a “common commentarial project” among Indian Mādhyamikas, more than a sharp division into camps.

A doxographic approach to Madhyamaka yields certain pictures, certain divides, certain sets of issues. From the doxographic view, we have evidence supporting a thematic connection between Bhāvaviveka and Śāntarakṣita and a thematic dissociation of these two from Buddhapālita and Candrakīrti that would support our use of “Svātantrika” for the former two and “Prāsaṅgika” for the latter two. Or, we may show thematic similarities between Bhāvaviveka and Candrakīrti that would support their classification as “pure Mādhyamikas” in contradistinction to Śāntarakṣita’s syncretic “YogācāraMadhyamaka.” Or, to revive earlier Tibetan distinctions, Jñānagarbha could be thematically dissociated from Śāntarakṣita and joined with Candrakīrti in supporting “what is renowned in the world” conventionally, in opposition to those, like Bhāvaviveka and Śāntarakṣita, who sought stronger philosophical grounding for the conventional world. All of these classifications possess exegetical merit and offer greater philosophical clarity.

In drawing these thematic connections, we cannot lose sight of historical patterns. When Bhāvaviveka in the sixth century criticized the logical procedures Buddhapālita utilized in commenting upon Nāgārjuna’s foundational Madhyamaka treatise and Candrakīrti in the seventh century rejected Bhāvaviveka’s logical methods (largely to deaf ears), we see competing interpretations of the Middle Way. However, only one of these interpretations gained influence over the next three hundred years. When Prajñākaramati, Atiśa, and Jayānanda revived Candrakīrti’s writings, these writings—at a great temporal and spatial distance from their creator—engendered expansive eleventhand twelfth-century Indian and Tibetan controversies. One focus of the controversy centered round the issue of whether a Mādhyamika may employ formal inferences in the manner developed by the great Buddhist logicians, Dignāga and Dharmakīrti, when arguing for Madhyamaka emptiness. Eleventhand twelfth-century Indian and Tibetan discussions of this logical, procedural issue expanded into wide-ranging areas of Buddhist ontology and gnoseology: the ways in which a Mādhyamika argued said a great deal about what that Mādhyamika held to exist, both from the mundane perspective and from the lofty vision of a Buddha. Finally, Candrakīrti gained a lively following that we might call a Prāsaṅgika movement.

Eleventh-century Tibetans who made the arduous journey to Kashmir or northeastern India found an Indian Buddhist world wrestling with the complex interplay of a ritual theory and praxis seemingly at odds with its metaphysical basis and well-established epistemological practices seemingly at odds with both ritual and metaphysics. We now turn to the activities of several of these Tibetan translators and the debates they touched off when casting this complex of issues in the fractured socio-political landscape of late eleventh- and early twelfth-century Tibet. The open textual horizons of eleventh-century India would coalesce quite quickly into Prāsaṅgika and Svātantrika “schools” of the Tibetan Middle Way.

 

How to cite this document:
© Kevin Vose, Resurrecting Candrakīrti (Wisdom Publications, 2009)

Creative Commons License
Resurrecting Candrakīrti by Kevin Vose is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivs 3.0 Unported License.
Based on a work at http://www.wisdompubs.org/book/resurrecting-candrakirti.
Permissions beyond the scope of this license may be available at http://www.wisdompubs.org/terms-use.